Next Contents Previous

3. PROFESSED FREQUENTISM VERSUS PRACTICED SUBJECTIVISM

3.1. HEP physicists ``are frequentist''

If one asks HEP physicists ``what is probability?'', one will realize immediately that they ``think they are'' frequentist. The same impression is got looking at the books and lecture notes they use [13]. Particularly significant, to get an overview of ideas and methods commonly used, are the PDG [3] and other booklets [14, 15] which have a kind of explicit (e.g. [3, 14]) or implicit (e.g. [15]) imprimatur of HEP organizations.

If, instead, one asks physicists what they think about probability as ``degree of belief'' the reaction is negative and can even be violent: ``science must be objective: there is no room for belief'', or ``I don't believe something. I assess it. This is no a matter for religion!''.

3.2. HEP physicists ``are Bayesian''

On the other hand, if one requires physicists to express their opinion about practical situations in condition of uncertainty, instead of just standard examination questions, one gets a completely different impression. One realize vividly that Science is indeed based on beliefs, very solid and well grounded beliefs, but they remain beliefs ``...in instrument types, in programs of experiment enquiry, in the trained, individual judgements about every local behavior of pieces of apparatus'' [16].

Physicists find it absolutely natural to talk about the probability of hypotheses, a concept for which there is no room in the frequentist approach. Also the intuitive way with which they figure out the result is, in fact, a probabilistic assessment on the true value. Try to ask what is the probability that the top quark mass is between 170 and 180 GeV. No one (12) will reply that the question has no sense, since ``the top quark mass is a constant of unknown value'' (as an orthodox frequentist should complain). They will simply answer that the probability is such and such percent, using the published value and ``error''. They are usually surprised if somebody tries to explain to them that they ``are not allowed'' to speak of probability of a true value.

Another word which physicists find scandalous is ``prior'' (``I don't want to be influenced by prejudices'' is the usual reply). But in reality priors play a very important role in laboratory routines, as well as at the moment of deciding that a paper is ready for publication. They allow experienced physicists to realize that something is going wrong, that a student has most probably made a serious mistake, that the result has not yet been corrected by all systematic effects, and so on. Unavoidably, priors generate some subtle cross correlations among results, and there are well known cases of the values of physics quantities slowly drifting from an initial point, with all subsequent results being included in the ``error bar'' of the previous experiment. But I think that there no one and nothing is to blame for the fact that these things happen (unless made on purpose): a strong evidence is needed before the scientific community radically changes its mind, and such evidence is often achieved after a long series of experiments. Moreover, very subtle systematic effects may affect the data, and it is not a simple task for an experimentalist to decide when all corrections have been applied, if he has no idea what the result should be.

3.3. Intuitive application of Bayes' theorem

There is an example which I like to give, in order to demonstrate that the intuitive reasoning which unconsciously transforms confidence intervals into probability intervals for the true value is, in fact, very close to the Bayes' theorem. Let us imagine we see a hunting dog in a forest and have to guess where the hunter is, knowing that there is a 50% probability that the dog is within 100 m around him. The terms of the analogy with respect to observable and true value are obvious. Everybody will answer immediately that, with 50% probability, the hunter is within 100 m from the dog. But everybody will also agree that the solution relies on some implicit assumptions: uniform prior distribution (of the hunter in the forest) and symmetric likelihood (the dog has no preferred direction, as far as we know, when he runs away from the hunter). Any variation in the assumptions leads to a different solution. And this is also easily recognized by physicists, expecially HEP physicists, who are aware of situations in which the prior is not flat (like the cases of a bremsstrahlung photon or of a cosmic ray spectrum) or the likelihood is not symmetric (not all detectors have a nice Gaussian response). In these situations intuition may still help a qualitatively guess to be made about the direction of the effect on the value of the measurand, but a formal application of the Bayesian ideas becomes crucial in order to state a result which is consistent with what can be honestly learned from data.

3.4. Bayes versus Monte Carlo

The fact that Bayesian inference is not currently used in HEP does not imply that non-trivial inverse problems remain unsolved, or that results are usually wrong. The solution often relies on extensive use of Monte Carlo (MC) simulation (13) and on intuition. The inverse problem is then treated as a direct one. The quantities of interest are considered as MC parameters, and are varied until the best statistical agreement between simulation output and experimental data is achieved. In principle, this is a simple numerical implementation of Maximum Likelihood, but in reality the prior distribution is also taken into account in the simulation when it is known to be non uniform (like in the aforementioned example of a cosmic ray experiment). So, in reality what it is often maximized is not the likelihood, but the Bayesian posterior (likelihood × prior), and, as said before, the result is intuitively considered to be a probabilistic statement for the true value. So, also in this case, the results are close to those obtainable by Bayesian inference, especially if the posterior is almost Gaussian (parabolic negative log-likelihood). Problems may occur, instead, when the ``not used'' prior is most likely not uniform, or when the posterior is very non-Gaussian. In the latter case the difference between mode and average of the distribution, and the evaluation of the uncertainty from the ``Delta(log-likelihood) = 1/2 rule'' can make quite a difference to the result.



12 Certainly one may find people aware of the ``sophistication'' of the frequentist approach, but these kinds of probabilistic statements are currently heard in conferences and no frequentist guru stands up to complain that the speaker is talking nonsense. Back.

13 If there is something in which HEP physicists really believe, it is Monte Carlo simulation! It plays a crucial role in all analyses, but sometimes its use as a multipurpose brute force problem solver is really unjustified and it can, from a cultural point of view, be counterproductive. For example, I have seen it applied to solve elementary problems which could be solved analytically, like ``proving'' that the variance of the sum of two random numbers is the sum of the variances. I once found a sentence at the end of the solution of a standard probability problem which I consider to be symptomatic of this brute force behaviour: ``if you don't trust logic, then you can make a little Monte Carlo...''. Back.

Next Contents Previous